nLab Boolean topos

Redirected from "Boolean toposes".
Contents

Context

Topos Theory

topos theory

Background

Toposes

Internal Logic

Topos morphisms

Extra stuff, structure, properties

Cohomology and homotopy

In higher category theory

Theorems

Contents

Definition

A Boolean topos is a topos that is also a Boolean category.

There are several conditions on a topos that are necessary and sufficient to be Boolean:

  • Every subobject has a complement (the general definition of Boolean category).
  • Every subobject lattice is a Boolean algebra.
  • The subobject classifier Ω\Omega is an internal Boolean algebra.
  • The maps ,:1Ω\top, \bot: 1 \to \Omega are a coproduct cone (so in particular, Ω1+1\Omega \cong 1 + 1, and in fact this is enough, because the map [,]:1+1Ω[\top, \bot]: 1 + 1 \to \Omega is always a monomorphism, and any monic endomorphism of Ω\Omega is an automorphism).

Warning

Let CC be a Boolean pretopos, i.e. a pretopos in which is also a Boolean category, and let Sh(C)Sh(C) be the classifying topos for CC. Then it does not follow that Sh(C)Sh(C) is Boolean. In fact, this is rarely the case, even if CC is the classifying pretopos for a theory in classical first-order logic. See Blass and Scedrov for a characterization of which classical first-order theories have Boolean classifying topoi – in particular, any such theory is 0\aleph_0-categorical. Nevertheless, as discussed below, Barr's theorem shows that any topos admits a surjection from a Boolean topos.

Properties

As a context for foundations

The internal logic of a Boolean topos with natural numbers object can serve as foundations for “ordinary” mathematics, except for that which relies on the axiom of choice. If you add the axiom of choice, then you get (an internal version of) ETCS; conversely, if you use an arbitrary topos, then you get constructive mathematics. (For some high-powered work, you may also need to add a version of the axiom of replacement or an axiom of Grothendieck universes.)

Every cartesian closed Boolean pretopos is in fact a topos. This is why ‘generalised predicativism’ (with function types but not power types) is necessarily a feature of constructive mathematics only.

Some characterisations

Proposition

For \mathcal{E} a topos, then the following are equivalent:

  1. \mathcal{E} is a Boolean topos;

  2. Every subtopos of \mathcal{E} is Boolean.

  3. Every subtopos of \mathcal{E} is an open subtopos.

  4. Every subtopos of \mathcal{E} is a closed subtopos.

(Johnstone, prop. A 4.5.22)

Proposition

Let jj be a Lawvere-Tierney topology on \mathcal{E}. Then j\mathcal{E}_j is Boolean iff there exists a subterminal object UU such that jj is the largest topology such that U1U\rightarrowtail 1 is jj-closed, or equivalently, that UU is a jj-sheaf.

Topologies jj satisfying the latter condition are called quasi-closed and sometimes denoted q(U)q(U). They can also be described by the Heyting algebra operations on Ω\Omega as the composite

ΩΩ×11×(χ U,χ U)Ω×Ω×Ω×1Ω×ΩΩ.\Omega\simeq\Omega\times 1\overset{1\times(\chi_U,\chi_U)}{\to}\Omega\times\Omega\times\Omega\overset{\Rightarrow\times 1}{\to}\Omega\times \Omega\overset{\Rightarrow}{\to}\Omega\quad .

The corresponding quasi-closed subtoposes Sh q(U)()Sh_{q(U)}(\mathcal{E}) are the double negation subtoposes Sh ¬¬(Sh c(U)())Sh_{\neg\neg}(Sh_{c(U)}(\mathcal{E})) of the closed subtoposes Sh c(U)()Sh_{c(U)}(\mathcal{E}) corresponding to the subterminal object UU.

For a proof of the proposition and the other assertions see (Johnstone 2002, p.220).

Proposition

\mathcal{E} is Boolean iff the only dense subtopos of \mathcal{E} is \mathcal{E} itself.

Proof. Suppose \mathcal{E} is Boolean. ¬¬=\mathcal{E}_{\neg\neg}=\mathcal{E} is the smallest dense subtopos (cf. double negation). Conservely, suppose \mathcal{E} is not Boolean then ¬¬\mathcal{E}_{\neg\neg} is a second dense subtopos.

Proposition

In a lattice of subtoposes the 2-valued Boolean toposes are the atoms.

See this proposition.

Proposition

Let \mathcal{E} be a topos. Then automorphisms of Ω\Omega correspond bijectively to closed Boolean subtoposes. The group operation on Aut(Ω)Aut(\Omega) corresponds to symmetric difference of subtoposes.

This result appears in Johnstone (1979). (See also Johnstone (2002), A1.6.11 pp.66-67.)

Examples

With excluded middle in the meta-logic, every well-pointed topos is a Boolean topos. This includes Set and models of ETCS.

The topos of sheaves on a Boolean algebra BB for the coherent topology is Boolean if and only if the Boolean algebra is finite. Indeed, in Sh(B)Sh(B) the sections of Ω\Omega over bBb \in B are the ideals of bB\downarrow b \leqslant B, while those of 1+11+1 are the principal ideals, and these coincide just when BB is finite.

The topos of canonical sheaves on a complete Boolean algebra is Boolean (note this includes the finite case above).

If \mathcal{E} is any topos, the category of sheaves for the double-negation topology is a Boolean subtopos of \mathcal{E}.

Any topos satisfying the axiom of choice is Boolean. This result is due to R. Diaconescu (1975); see excluded middle for a brief discussion.

Barr's theorem implies that any topos \mathcal{E} can be covered by a Boolean topos \mathcal{F}, in the sense of there being a surjective geometric morphism f:f \colon \mathcal{F} \to \mathcal{E}.

Relation to measure theory

Boolean toposes are closely related to measurable spaces (e.g Jackson 06, Henry 14).

References

General

  • Andreas Blass, Andrej Scedrov, Boolean Classifying Topoi , JPAA 28 (1983) pp.15-30.

  • Radu Diaconescu, Axiom of Choice and Complementation , Trans. AMS 51 no.1 (1975) pp.176-178. (pdf)

  • Peter Johnstone, Automorphisms of Ω\Omega , Algebra Universalis 9 (1979) pp.1-7.

  • Peter Johnstone, Sketches of an Elephant vols. I,II, Oxford UP 2002. (A4.5.22, D3.4, D4.5)

Relation to measure theory

On relation of Boolean toposes to measure theory:

Last revised on November 22, 2024 at 11:50:11. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.